Mark Hannam
homeaboutarticlesessaysreviews

reviews

One substance, many voters
A Revolution of the Mind
by Jonathan Israel
(Princeton University Press, 2010)

Printable version

Larry Temkin
Being Good in a World of Need

Peter E Gordon
Migrants in the Profane

Janek Wasserman
The Marginal Revolutionaries

Michael Lewis
The Fifth Risk

Brooke Harrington
Capital without Borders

Jo Wolff
Ethics and Public Policy

Daniel Halliday
The Inheritance of Wealth:
Justice, equality, and the
right to bequeath


Martin Jay
Reason after Its Eclipse: On Late Critical Theory

Lesley Sherratt
Can Microfinance Work?

Boudewijn de Bruin
Ethics and the Financial Crisis: Why Incompetence is Worse than Greed

Nicholas Morris &
David Vines

Capital Failure: Rebuilding Trust in Financial Services

Looking at Warhol's Flowers

Jeremy Worman
Swimming With Diana Dors

Michael Ignatieff
Fire and Ashes: Success and
Failure in Politics


Jon Elster
Securities Against Misrule

Jesse Norman
Edmund Burke: Philosopher, Politician, Prophet

Michael Sandel
What Money Can't Buy: The Moral Limits of Markets

Hilary Mantel
Bring up the Bodies

Philip Coggan
Paper Promises: Money, Debt and the New World Order

Jeffrey Friedman &
Wladimir Kraus

Engineering the Financial Crisis: Systemic Risk and the Failure of Regulation

Jeremy Worman
Fragmented

Martin Gayford
Man with a Blue Scarf

Raghuram Rajan
Fault Lines

Jonathan Israel
A Revolution of the Mind

T. J. Clark
The Sight of Death

Beautiful Facts:
Recent Paintings by
Alison Turnbull


Jacqueline Novogratz
The Blue Sweater

Matthew Bishop &
Michael Green

Philanthrocapitalism

Camilla Howalt

James Griffin
On Human Rights

Ronald Cohen
The Second Bounce of the Ball

Edward Craig
The Mind of God and the Works of Man

"If it is now asked whether we at present live in an enlightened age, the answer is: No, but we do live in an age of enlightenment". If Jonathan Israel is to be believed, Kant was wrong even as he made this claim in 1784. Not because enlightenment had already been achieved; rather, because Kant lived in an age of two, competing enlightenment movements.

These two Enlightenments - which Israel calls the Radical Enlightenment and the Moderate Enlightenment - are best distinguished by their philosophical content. In particular, by their differing attitudes to the idea of substance and the idea of human equality.

Ranged against both of these, Israel says, were the forces of conservative thought - the Counter Enlightenment - which championed the traditional values of orthodox religion and monarchy, and which resisted the attempt to subject these traditional values, and the power structures they supported, to critical examination. Disputes between thinkers whom Israel classifies as Radical and thinkers whom he classifies as Moderates were primarily disputes about how far the rational criticism of traditional values should go.

On the one hand, in the Moderate camp, Descartes set out a method for the new philosophy. Although he was willing to subject all of his beliefs to doubt, his method led him to propose a universe of two substances and an accommodation with traditional Christian theology in the form of a providential God who did not deceive us. Descartes' deism became the template for other Moderate Enlightenment thinkers: Locke, Voltaire and Kant, for example.

In the Radical camp, Spinoza argued that there was and could only be one substance. Whether we call this substance "God" or "Nature", Spinoza's ontological radicalism was a direct assault on traditional Christian and Jewish theology. His work became the inspiration both for Christian Unitarians and materialist atheists, including Diderot and d'Holbach. Central to the Radical Enlightenment's attack on traditional values was its rejection of the idea of providence and the belief in final causes in nature and history.

Disputes over the idea of providence - the notion that God has revealed truths about morality and models for good governance though the course of human history - led directly to disputes about politics. The Moderates were suspicious of making radical change to political arrangements that had been passed down over many generations, and some doubted the capacity of the common people to employ the faculty of reason: Voltaire wrote that "nine-tenths of mankind do not deserve to be enlightened".

The Radicals, by contrast, believed that morality and political order should be built upon reason not tradition; that despotic systems of government should be overthrown; that all men (and, in some cases, all women too) were capable of reasoned judgement; and that democracy was the ideal form of government.

Israel observes that religious scepticism and political radicalism did not always go hand in hand. His dividing line is not drawn between religious conservatives and atheist democrats, but between philosophical monists, who embraced secular morality and democratic politics, and providential dualists, who wanted to reform clerical and autocratic abuses, but were content to preserve the hierarchical social order and a mixed form of government.

A Revolution of the Mind provides a highly condensed version of Jonathan Israel's account of the two Enlightenments. Based on lectures given during 2008 to commemorate the life and work of Isaiah Berlin, this volume, like Berlin's best work in intellectual history, is an extended essay. Those wishing to follow Israel's argument in more detail should refer to his three volume history, of which the first two volumes - Radical Enlightenment (2001) and Contested Enlightenment (2006) - already run to 1,600 pages of text and 140 pages of bibliography.

Why bother to undertake such a lengthy read? First, Israel's account challenges a version of the history of modern democracy, which emphasizes the correspondence between the Protestant belief in the equality of all believers with the democratic belief in the equality of all citizens. But for Israel it is Spinoza's writings - not Luther's - that provide the inspiration for modern democratic theory. The Spinozist lineage allows us to appreciate better the secular foundations and universal appeal of modern democracy, rather than treating it primarily as a Christian- and European-inspired form of government.

Second, Israel emphasizes the role of philosophical ideas as a force for social and political change. He claims that a revolution in thought led to revolutions in society and in government; that ideas can and do change the world; that philosophy is not merely a sublimate of the underlying social structure. This, then, is a version of history that champions the importance of philosophical ideas in general, as well as championing a particular set of Radical Enlightenment ideas about substance and equality.

Printable version

© Mark Hannam 2010

back to top

home| about|articles|essays|reviews|contact